People's Democracy(Weekly Organ of the Communist Party of India (Marxist) |
Vol. XXXVII
No. 02 January 13, 2013 |
Leninism
and Class Consciousness
Prabhat
Patnaik
A BASIC
proposition of Leninism is that theoretical understanding that
leads to the
formation of class consciousness comes to the proletariat from
“outside;” the
proletariat does not spontaneously achieve revolutionary class
consciousness.
This idea did not originate with Lenin. It was contained in
the Communist Manifesto
itself, where Marx
and Engels had discussed three sources from which the
proletariat drew
enlightenment in organising itself as a class: first, the
bourgeoisie itself which
dragged the proletariat into the political arena by seeking
its support for
fighting battles against the feudal lords and the other class
enemies it faced,
and therefore supplied the proletariat “with its own elements
of political and
general education;” second, sections of the ruling classes
which were thrown
into the ranks of the proletariat with the progress of modern
industry, and
supplied the proletariat “with fresh elements of enlightenment
and progress;”
and thirdly, a portion of the bourgeois ideologists, who had
raised themselves
to the level of “comprehending theoretically the historical
movement as a
whole” and went over to the side of the proletariat. In short,
the idea that
the proletariat organises itself as a class with the
“enlightenment” that comes
to it from “outside,” predated Lenin and was already there in
the Manifesto. But
Lenin gave this idea both
a centrality and a concrete shape that it did not have
earlier.
FROM CLASS INSTINCT
TO CLASS CONSCIOUSNESS
Many,
including some sympathisers of the Left, see in this
proposition, about theory
having to come to the proletariat from “outside,” the genesis
of an
anti-democratic, authoritarian trend that according to them
leads inevitably to
a dictatorship over
the proletariat
rather than a dictatorship of the
proletariat. A part of the answer to this criticism of Lenin
was given earlier
(People’s Democracy, December
30), where
it was argued that “democracy” itself, if it is to mean not
just an
accommodation of, and negotiations between, different
“identities” and interest
groups, but a transcendence of these specific “identities” for
the creation of
a new fraternity, has to be brought to the people from
“outside.” People do not
spontaneously acquire a “democratic consciousness” any more
than the
proletariat spontaneously acquires a socialist consciousness.
“Democratic
consciousness” in this sense, of rising above all forms of
specific identity
consciousness, to see oneself as a member of a fraternity of
equals, as a
citizen on a par with other citizens, has to be brought to the
people from
“outside.”
True,
even this attenuated notion of democracy, as a process of
negotiations between
different identity groups, itself represents an advance: when
dalits confront
upper castes for their
rights and the latter are forced to negotiate with them, or
the state mediates
between the two, this very fact already entails a massive blow
against the old
order; but it still does not represent an overcoming of the
old order, which
can only happen when the whole hierarchical caste system with
its ideology of
inequality disappears
altogether.
Authentic democracy must mean such a disappearance, and the
conception of such
a democracy comes, not necessarily geographically, but
epistemologically, from
“outside.”
But
a second part of the answer to the critics of Leninism lies in
the fact that
Lenin’s position has been persistently misinterpreted. It is
not that the
proletariat consists of an inert mass which has to be prepared
for carrying out
a revolutionary transformation by filling its mind with a
theory brought from
“outside;” i.e. that it represents, to change the metaphor, a
clean slate upon
which the theorists from “outside,” the “ideologists who have
theoretically
comprehended the historical movement as a whole” (to use the
words of the Manifesto),
can write the programme of
the revolution, in which case the proletariat merely becomes
the cannon-fodder
for the grand ideas of a revolutionary intelligentsia which
acquires power on behalf
of the proletariat to establish a dictatorship, no matter how
benevolent, upon
it. Such is not the Leninist conception. The proletariat is
not the “object,”
and revolutionary intellectuals in leading positions in the
vanguard party the
“subjects” of the historical process surrounding the
revolution. What Leninism
holds is that the proletariat has a “class instinct” because of which it becomes at all receptive to the
revolutionary
theory brought to it from “outside.” The role of the
theory brought from
“outside” is, in other words, not to write revolutionary ideas
on a clean
slate, but to enable the proletariat to make the journey from
“class instinct”
to “class consciousness.”
DIALECTICS
OF
THEORY
AND PRACTICE
This
journey too cannot be seen as being effected solely through
the intervention of
theory. The struggle of the working class on its material
demands relating to
wages and working conditions, leads to the formation of
“combinations” and the
development of a “trade union consciousness.” With the
intervention of the
bourgeois state on the side of the employers during these
struggles, the trade
union consciousness itself begins to be supplemented by a
political
understanding, namely, that it is not only the capitalists who
constitute their
class opponents but also the state which acts on their behalf.
Marx had
discussed this process of the proletariat acquiring a
political understanding
from its own experience of struggle in The
Poverty of Philosophy. But this self-movement of the
proletariat cannot
spontaneously carry it to the acquisition of a revolutionary
class
consciousness. The introduction of theory from “outside” is
necessary to
complete the transition.
Not
to recognise this is tantamount to making the palpably invalid
claim that
theory can be acquired entirely from experience, that there is
no autonomous
process of theoretical development, on the basis of a
theoretical practice that
operates on concepts bequeathed from the past by theoretical
practice
undertaken in the past. The workers, in short, make the
transition from “class
instinct” to “class consciousness” through the acquisition of
theory from
“outside” but in the
course of their own
practice of struggle.
A
dialectics between theory and practice is what underlies the
development of revolutionary
proletarian class consciousness; in the absence of such a
dialectics there will
be a mere duality, a separation, and a disjunction, which can
manifest itself
in a variety of ways. Krupskaya, in her Memories
of Lenin, gives several instances of Lenin’s concern
that such duality must
not creep into (what was then) the “social democratic”
movement. He was, for
example, insistent on bringing workers into committees, and
also on the
convergence between the current of party work and the
self-activity of the
workers.
The
“class instinct” of the workers itself cannot be seen as a
mere static
attribute; it is something that also develops and sharpens
itself, even though
it does not spontaneously give rise to revolutionary “class
consciousness.” Hence,
Leninism is not about persons epistemologically located
outside the working
class and dictating to the working class what it should do or
pushing the
working class into doing something that they have
theoretically arrived at as a
panacea for social ills. The working class would not even
respond to them if
that was the case; it responds because its own “class
instincts,” getting
sharpened in the process of its own struggles, enable it to
perceive the
validity of the theory that comes to it from “outside.”
ON
DEPOLITICISATION
IN
EX-SOCIALIST COUNTRIES
The
problem of how the working class got depoliticised in the
socialist countries
that existed earlier, because of which there was no serious
working class
resistance to the collapse of socialism, needs proper
analysis; but to question
the basic Leninist proposition and to hold that proposition
responsible for this
depoliticisation is completely without any basis. Putting it
differently, the
absence of convergence between theory and working class
practice must of course
be examined, but this absence of convergence should not be
taken to mean that
theory is unnecessary or that it can be acquired
spontaneously.
This
“class instinct” of the proletariat as it develops through its
struggles, which
makes it receptive to theory, is closely linked to the
question of socialist
democracy. A basic presupposition of democracy is that the
common people can be
discerning enough to make choices even on so-called technical
issues; i.e. that
decisions about the course that a society must follow are not
something that
must be left only to the experts. This presupposition itself
will be questioned
by many. In the case of socialism they would raise an
additional issue, namely,
that since no course would be followed that jeopardises the
future of the revolution,
no socialist would actually risk this future by leaving
decisions to the
proletarian masses. Since too much is at stake, a
revolutionary society would
necessarily bypass proletarian sovereignty and gravitate
towards taking decisions
exclusively at the level of the vanguard where theoretical
competence and
expertise are concentrated. They would therefore argue that a
socialist
society, keen to defend the revolution, will necessarily
bypass democracy.
But
the proletariat’s “class instinct” makes it averse to
jeopardising the future
of the revolution; it therefore would favour decisions that it
believes would carry
the revolution forward. This implies not only that leaving
decision making to
the proletariat at large is not harmful for the revolution,
but that on the
contrary not doing so is fraught with adverse consequences for
the revolution. This
is why a socialist society would need to respect proletarian
sovereignty in decision
making in the interests of the revolution itself.
Put
differently, the fact that the proletariat, even though it is
theoretically
less advanced than the intellectuals in the vanguard
organisation, has a class
instinct that enables it to defend the revolution against
wrong theory (and
also eventually against theory whose wrongness, though not
immediately obvious,
becomes apparent over time), constitutes the basis for
socialist democracy, for
making the proletarian masses the ultimate arbiters in crucial
decisions.
There
is, in other words, no inherent tendency, derived from the
theory of socialism,
for excluding the people, essentially the proletariat, from
exercising
sovereignty in decision making in a socialist society. The
perception that the
Leninist view of “theory” being brought from “outside”
militates against
socialist democracy is without any basis. Likewise, the
perception that the
future of the revolution would be jeopardised if the
sovereignty of the people
in decision making is institutionalised, is also without any
basis. “Theory”
coming from “outside” is perfectly compatible with the
practice of democracy
under socialism. And what is more, since socialism, implying
social ownership
of the means of production, overcomes the “spontaneity” of
capitalism where the
system is driven by its own immanent tendencies and the
individual participants
within the system are reduced to being mere objects, authentic
democracy can
only be realised under socialism.