People's Democracy(Weekly Organ of the Communist Party of India (Marxist) |
Vol. XXXVI
No. 29 July 22, 2012 |
The
Poverty of Anti-Unionism
Prabhat
Patnaik
BOURGEOIS
economics, from very early on,
has sought to argue that trade unions constitute an
undesirable phenomenon.
This is true not just of what Marx had called “vulgar
economics” which
succeeded classical political economy, but even of the later
exponents of
classical political economy itself, like John Stuart Mill,
who had propounded a
“Wages Fund” theory that went as follows: at any time in
society there was a
fund out of which wages were advanced; if there were some
unionised workers who
could raise their wages by virtue of being unionised, then
this meant less
being left over for the non-unionised workers. Trade unions
therefore could not
benefit all workers;
they could only
benefit some workers at
the expense of
the others. They therefore necessarily exacerbated
inequalities among
workers.
VARIOUS
ARGUMENTS
This
view which was articulated by a
follower of Mill, Citizen Weston, at a meeting of the
International Workingmen’s
Association (the First International), was critiqued by Marx
in a speech that
took the form of a well-known pamphlet, Wages,
Prices and Profits, which outlined the basics of
Marx’s as yet unpublished
opus, Capital,
and which argued that
workers as a whole
could benefit
through union action, in the form of higher wages, at the expense of profits. A part of the
revenue that would have
accrued to the capitalists would accrue instead to the
workers as higher wages;
and correspondingly, in lieu of the products that would have
been produced to
meet the capitalists’ demand arising from this revenue,
different products
would be produced to meet the workers’ additional demand.
After
1870 when “neo-classical economics”
originated, whose exponents were authors like Marshall,
Walras, Menger and Jevons,
a different theoretical argument was advanced against trade
unionism. This went
as follows. In a capitalist economy, price adjustments
occurred to “clear” all
markets; i.e. through adjustments, a set of prices got
established at which
whatever was supplied was exactly equal to what was
demanded. The labour market
too “cleared” at a particular real wage rate, so that if
this real wage rate
came to be established, which it
automatically would if the market was allowed to function
freely, there
would be full employment in the economy. It followed from
this theory that if
we actually have unemployment at the going real wage, then
the reason for it lies
in the fact that the market was not
allowed to function freely, i.e. the real wage rate
was not allowed to drop
to the level required for achieving full employment; it was
artificially kept
up.
Trade
union action according to this view
therefore necessarily led to unemployment. Such action was
obviously
superfluous if it only succeeded in achieving for workers a
real wage rate that
was the “market-clearing” real wage rate, since that rate
would obtain anyway
through the spontaneous functioning of markets, even without
unions. Trade
union action became meaningful only if it got the workers a
wage rate in excess
of what the free and spontaneous functioning of the labour
market would have
fetched them. But if such a wage got established, then there
would necessarily
be unemployment. Hence if trade union action is effective,
then it must produce
unemployment. Some workers’ gain in short is other workers’
loss.
So
influential was this view, namely that
unemployment under capitalism was the result of “excessively
high” real wages,
that in the midst of the Great Depression of the 1930s,
there were frantic
efforts to curtail wages for reducing unemployment, until
Roosevelt’s New Deal
made a break with this policy.
NEO-CLASSICAL
FALLACY
A
basic fallacy (among others) of this
“neo-classical” argument was the following: if “excessively
high” real wages,
enforced by trade unions, was the cause of unemployment,
then we should notice
only unemployment, while there should be
full capacity use of the capital stock (in the sense
that no piece of
equipment, which is not loss-making at the going real wage
rate, should be
lying idle). We
should not in other
words be witnessing both
unemployed
labour and idle capital occurring together. But this
is precisely what we
noticed in abundance during the Great Depression of the
1930s, and precisely
what has characterised capitalism throughout its entire
history, though of
course to a lesser extent. As Michael Kalecki, the renowned
Marxist economist,
has said: “..…chronic underutilisation of equipment….. was a
frequent
phenomenon in developed capitalist economies”.
Such
chronic underutilisation of equipment
coexisting with chronic unemployment suggests that the
constraint on the level
of activity in a capitalist economy comes from the side of
demand and not from
“excessively high” wages. Capitalism in short is essentially
a
“demand-constrained” system. But then trade union action, by
raising real
wages, increases
demand and hence
employment. Far from reducing employment, trade union
action therefore
results in higher employment than would have prevailed
otherwise.
The
matter can be explained as follows: a
rise in real wages, given the level of technology, and hence
the level of
labour productivity in any period, must mean an increase in
the share of wages
in output and a decline in the share of profits. Now the
capitalists have a
lower consumption ratio out of profits than the workers have
out of their
wages. Hence a shift in income distribution from the
capitalists to the
workers, tends to raise the overall consumption ratio in the
economy. For any
given level of investment then, which is not much affected
by such relative
share movements since it depends much more on expectations
about the growth of
the economy, the level of output and employment increases if
the share of wages
increases. Trade union action, by raising real wages, for
any given level of
labour productivity, at the expense of the profit-share,
succeeds therefore in
achieving both higher
wages and higher
employment, and
shifts the
economy to a higher level of output.
CAPITALISM:
A DEMAND-
CONSTRAINED
SYSTEM
The
“neo-classical” argument has been
sought to be revived in a slightly different form in the
recent period. This
talks not of employment and unemployment, but assumes that full employment gets achieved,
taking the unionised and the non-unionised workers
together. If there were
no unions at all, then all workers would get the same wage
rate and the level
of that would be one where all of them were employed. But
unionisation means
that some workers get a higher wage than this “equal”
“market-clearing” wage;
this reduces employment in the unionised sector, forcing
more workers into
non-unionised sectors, where overcrowding reduces the wage
rate. If we compare
a situation where trade unions exist, with one where they do
not, then,
according to this argument, employment remains the same in
both cases, i.e. at full
employment, but the unionised workers get higher wages, which cause a reduction in the wages of
non-unionised workers through
overcrowding. Trade unions in short improve the lot of
some workers while
worsening that of others.
This
argument has been used, among others,
to press for “labour market flexibility” in the Indian
economy. And the fallacy
of this argument, again, lies in not recognising the
essential nature of
capitalism as a “demand-constrained” system. It is
invariably characterised by
unutilised capacity, even in sectors of the economy where
the workforce is
unionised. And what appears as “employment” outside these
sectors is often
“disguised unemployment” (e.g. shoe-shine boys), whose
reduction does not
reduce output. The existence of substantial unutilised
capacity can be
established very simply in the case of the Indian economy.
Let
us not even consider what “full
capacity” output in the economy may be; let us just take the
peak output already
achieved in any given month of
the year as full capacity output (even though that may
itself entail
significant unutilised capacity). By taking the actual
output in any month
relative to this peak, we get a measure of the degree of
capacity utilisation
for any given month, on the basis of which we can measure
“unutilised capacity”
for the year as a whole (or for quarters within the year).
Even on this
measure, the degree of capacity utilisation in the Indian
manufacturing sector
(which is typically where “labour market flexibility” is
supposed to be
introduced), has been lower in every subsequent quarter
compared to the third
quarter of 2009-10. In other words, the Indian manufacturing
sector has been
the site of significant unutilised capacity in the recent
period, and the reason
obviously is inadequate demand for domestic goods.
STRIKING
STATISTICS
In
this situation, if real wages of unionised
workers are reduced, by, say, removing trade unions from the
scene altogether,
then the demand for domestic goods will fall even more (for
reasons discussed
above), which would
worsen the conditions
of even the workers who were hitherto non-unionised.
Conversely, trade
unions, by raising the wages of unionised workers, increase
the level of demand
for domestically-produced goods, both by raising aggregate
consumption demand
and also by reducing the share of imports within this
aggregate because their
demand is less import-intensive than capitalists’ demand;
and this contributes
to higher demand for labour in the economy and hence higher
incomes even of
non-unionised workers. It follows that
trade union action benefits not only the unionised workers
but also,
indirectly, the non-unionised ones. It is not a case
of gains for some
workers and losses for others, but gains for all workers
because of trade union
action.
These
gains are invariably associated with
a decline in the relative share of profits, though not in
the absolute amount
of profits. Since with the rise in workers’ incomes output
also expands because
of the relaxation of the demand constraint, the rise in such
incomes does not
entail a fall in the income of the capitalists. But the relative share of profits does decline, which
in turn entails a
reduction in income inequalities in society as a whole.
There
are some striking statistics from the
United States, put together by Colin Gordon of the Economic
Policy Institute. Taking a
long historical period, between 1918 and
2008, it turns out that there is a remarkable negative
correlation between the
share of income going to the top 10 per cent of the
population, and the
proportion of workers who are members of trade unions. In
periods when union
membership increases the share of income going to the top 10
per cent of the
population declines; and likewise when union membership
declines the share
going to the top 10 per cent increases, as has been
happening in the last 30
years in that country.
Trade
unions, in short, do not just raise
incomes for their members. They play a larger social role,
of raising aggregate
demand and employment in the economy, even to the benefit of
the non-unionised
workers, and keeping down income inequalities. Since
democracy gets seriously
attenuated by large income inequalities, trade unions are an
essential
instrument for the maintenance of democracy. Those who argue
in favour of
“labour market flexibility,” which amounts in effect to
doing away with trade
unions, are not just propounding a wrong theory; they are
undermining the
foundations of democracy.